What did Turing mean when saying that “machines cannot give rise to surprises” is due to a fallacy? ...

Is the time—manner—place ordering of adverbials an oversimplification?

Is a copyright notice with a non-existent name be invalid?

What is "Lambda" in Heston's original paper on stochastic volatility models?

How does TikZ render an arc?

How to resize main filesystem

In musical terms, what properties are varied by the human voice to produce different words / syllables?

Does a random sequence of vectors span a Hilbert space?

Why not use the yoke to control yaw, as well as pitch and roll?

How could a hydrazine and N2O4 cloud (or it's reactants) show up in weather radar?

Understanding piped commands in GNU/Linux

Russian equivalents of おしゃれは足元から (Every good outfit starts with the shoes)

Is the Mordenkainen's Sword spell underpowered?

Short story about astronauts fertilizing soil with their own bodies

How to ask rejected full-time candidates to apply to teach individual courses?

Is this Kuo-toa homebrew race balanced?

Is there a verb for listening stealthily?

Did pre-Columbian Americans know the spherical shape of the Earth?

.bashrc alias for a command with fixed second parameter

2018 MacBook Pro won't let me install macOS High Sierra 10.13 from USB installer

The test team as an enemy of development? And how can this be avoided?

Determine whether an integer is a palindrome

Baking rewards as operations

Found this skink in my tomato plant bucket. Is he trapped? Or could he leave if he wanted?

Is there a spell that can create a permanent fire?



What did Turing mean when saying that “machines cannot give rise to surprises” is due to a fallacy?



Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern)
Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara
Unicorn Meta Zoo #1: Why another podcast?What does sublinear space mean for Turing machines?Simulate a regular Turing Machine with one that cannot write blanksExamples of processes / problems that cannot be tackled by Turing MachinesWhat is the limit for Turing machines with 2 states and 3 symbols that halt?Disprove that a function exists that counts the turing machines that halt on $epsilon$Language of Turing machines that never visit some given stateWhat does it mean when its said that most Turing Machines are not programmable?What does “effective enumeration” in Turing machines mean?Proof that Turing machines and computers have same powerWhy cannot we enumerate all Turing machines that have no fixed point?












24












$begingroup$


I encountered below statement by Alan M. Turing here:




"The view that machines cannot give rise to surprises is due, I
believe, to a fallacy to which philosophers and mathematicians are
particularly subject. This is the assumption that as soon as a fact is
presented to a mind all consequences of that fact spring into the mind
simultaneously with it. It is a very useful assumption under many
circumstances, but one too easily forgets that it is false."




I am not a native English speaker. Could anyone explain it in plain English?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$


We're looking for long answers that provide some explanation and context. Don't just give a one-line answer; explain why your answer is right, ideally with citations. Answers that don't include explanations may be removed.










  • 2




    $begingroup$
    perhaps, it's better suited for philosophy portal rather to hard science like CS
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    2 days ago






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Bulat I was going to say the same -- and redirect to English Language Learners -- but then I realised that there is some CS-related content that can be explained in an answer, which probably wouldn't be picked up on, in other parts of Stack Exchange.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    A good example is iteration of the transformation z := z² + c, where z and c are complex numbers. What happens if I take any starting point on the plane z and iterate, will the number go to infinity or not? An ordinary fellow would say, yeah, this will give you two regions or maybe a few more where the value goes to zero and for the rest it goes to infinity. Relatively unsurprising. Then Mandelbrot comes along and actually plots the regions on the the plane defined by this simple "machine". As the result comes out of the dotmatrix printer, this simple "machine" proves itself ... weird.
    $endgroup$
    – David Tonhofer
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    Facebook and other social media are a great example of this... A lot of the consequences of their algorithms are not something that was expected by the creators (or anyone really).
    $endgroup$
    – aslum
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    A rather quirky individual once referred to this using a fire metaphor: "The bigger you build your bonfire of knowledge, the more darkness is revealed to your startled eye"
    $endgroup$
    – JacobIRR
    2 days ago
















24












$begingroup$


I encountered below statement by Alan M. Turing here:




"The view that machines cannot give rise to surprises is due, I
believe, to a fallacy to which philosophers and mathematicians are
particularly subject. This is the assumption that as soon as a fact is
presented to a mind all consequences of that fact spring into the mind
simultaneously with it. It is a very useful assumption under many
circumstances, but one too easily forgets that it is false."




I am not a native English speaker. Could anyone explain it in plain English?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$


We're looking for long answers that provide some explanation and context. Don't just give a one-line answer; explain why your answer is right, ideally with citations. Answers that don't include explanations may be removed.










  • 2




    $begingroup$
    perhaps, it's better suited for philosophy portal rather to hard science like CS
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    2 days ago






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Bulat I was going to say the same -- and redirect to English Language Learners -- but then I realised that there is some CS-related content that can be explained in an answer, which probably wouldn't be picked up on, in other parts of Stack Exchange.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    A good example is iteration of the transformation z := z² + c, where z and c are complex numbers. What happens if I take any starting point on the plane z and iterate, will the number go to infinity or not? An ordinary fellow would say, yeah, this will give you two regions or maybe a few more where the value goes to zero and for the rest it goes to infinity. Relatively unsurprising. Then Mandelbrot comes along and actually plots the regions on the the plane defined by this simple "machine". As the result comes out of the dotmatrix printer, this simple "machine" proves itself ... weird.
    $endgroup$
    – David Tonhofer
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    Facebook and other social media are a great example of this... A lot of the consequences of their algorithms are not something that was expected by the creators (or anyone really).
    $endgroup$
    – aslum
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    A rather quirky individual once referred to this using a fire metaphor: "The bigger you build your bonfire of knowledge, the more darkness is revealed to your startled eye"
    $endgroup$
    – JacobIRR
    2 days ago














24












24








24


6



$begingroup$


I encountered below statement by Alan M. Turing here:




"The view that machines cannot give rise to surprises is due, I
believe, to a fallacy to which philosophers and mathematicians are
particularly subject. This is the assumption that as soon as a fact is
presented to a mind all consequences of that fact spring into the mind
simultaneously with it. It is a very useful assumption under many
circumstances, but one too easily forgets that it is false."




I am not a native English speaker. Could anyone explain it in plain English?










share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$




I encountered below statement by Alan M. Turing here:




"The view that machines cannot give rise to surprises is due, I
believe, to a fallacy to which philosophers and mathematicians are
particularly subject. This is the assumption that as soon as a fact is
presented to a mind all consequences of that fact spring into the mind
simultaneously with it. It is a very useful assumption under many
circumstances, but one too easily forgets that it is false."




I am not a native English speaker. Could anyone explain it in plain English?







turing-machines computability computation-models






share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











share|cite|improve this question









New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited 4 hours ago









Discrete lizard

4,59811538




4,59811538






New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









asked 2 days ago









smwikipediasmwikipedia

21725




21725




New contributor




smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






smwikipedia is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.



We're looking for long answers that provide some explanation and context. Don't just give a one-line answer; explain why your answer is right, ideally with citations. Answers that don't include explanations may be removed.




We're looking for long answers that provide some explanation and context. Don't just give a one-line answer; explain why your answer is right, ideally with citations. Answers that don't include explanations may be removed.









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    perhaps, it's better suited for philosophy portal rather to hard science like CS
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    2 days ago






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Bulat I was going to say the same -- and redirect to English Language Learners -- but then I realised that there is some CS-related content that can be explained in an answer, which probably wouldn't be picked up on, in other parts of Stack Exchange.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    A good example is iteration of the transformation z := z² + c, where z and c are complex numbers. What happens if I take any starting point on the plane z and iterate, will the number go to infinity or not? An ordinary fellow would say, yeah, this will give you two regions or maybe a few more where the value goes to zero and for the rest it goes to infinity. Relatively unsurprising. Then Mandelbrot comes along and actually plots the regions on the the plane defined by this simple "machine". As the result comes out of the dotmatrix printer, this simple "machine" proves itself ... weird.
    $endgroup$
    – David Tonhofer
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    Facebook and other social media are a great example of this... A lot of the consequences of their algorithms are not something that was expected by the creators (or anyone really).
    $endgroup$
    – aslum
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    A rather quirky individual once referred to this using a fire metaphor: "The bigger you build your bonfire of knowledge, the more darkness is revealed to your startled eye"
    $endgroup$
    – JacobIRR
    2 days ago














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    perhaps, it's better suited for philosophy portal rather to hard science like CS
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    2 days ago






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Bulat I was going to say the same -- and redirect to English Language Learners -- but then I realised that there is some CS-related content that can be explained in an answer, which probably wouldn't be picked up on, in other parts of Stack Exchange.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    A good example is iteration of the transformation z := z² + c, where z and c are complex numbers. What happens if I take any starting point on the plane z and iterate, will the number go to infinity or not? An ordinary fellow would say, yeah, this will give you two regions or maybe a few more where the value goes to zero and for the rest it goes to infinity. Relatively unsurprising. Then Mandelbrot comes along and actually plots the regions on the the plane defined by this simple "machine". As the result comes out of the dotmatrix printer, this simple "machine" proves itself ... weird.
    $endgroup$
    – David Tonhofer
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    Facebook and other social media are a great example of this... A lot of the consequences of their algorithms are not something that was expected by the creators (or anyone really).
    $endgroup$
    – aslum
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    A rather quirky individual once referred to this using a fire metaphor: "The bigger you build your bonfire of knowledge, the more darkness is revealed to your startled eye"
    $endgroup$
    – JacobIRR
    2 days ago








2




2




$begingroup$
perhaps, it's better suited for philosophy portal rather to hard science like CS
$endgroup$
– Bulat
2 days ago




$begingroup$
perhaps, it's better suited for philosophy portal rather to hard science like CS
$endgroup$
– Bulat
2 days ago




2




2




$begingroup$
@Bulat I was going to say the same -- and redirect to English Language Learners -- but then I realised that there is some CS-related content that can be explained in an answer, which probably wouldn't be picked up on, in other parts of Stack Exchange.
$endgroup$
– David Richerby
2 days ago




$begingroup$
@Bulat I was going to say the same -- and redirect to English Language Learners -- but then I realised that there is some CS-related content that can be explained in an answer, which probably wouldn't be picked up on, in other parts of Stack Exchange.
$endgroup$
– David Richerby
2 days ago




5




5




$begingroup$
A good example is iteration of the transformation z := z² + c, where z and c are complex numbers. What happens if I take any starting point on the plane z and iterate, will the number go to infinity or not? An ordinary fellow would say, yeah, this will give you two regions or maybe a few more where the value goes to zero and for the rest it goes to infinity. Relatively unsurprising. Then Mandelbrot comes along and actually plots the regions on the the plane defined by this simple "machine". As the result comes out of the dotmatrix printer, this simple "machine" proves itself ... weird.
$endgroup$
– David Tonhofer
2 days ago






$begingroup$
A good example is iteration of the transformation z := z² + c, where z and c are complex numbers. What happens if I take any starting point on the plane z and iterate, will the number go to infinity or not? An ordinary fellow would say, yeah, this will give you two regions or maybe a few more where the value goes to zero and for the rest it goes to infinity. Relatively unsurprising. Then Mandelbrot comes along and actually plots the regions on the the plane defined by this simple "machine". As the result comes out of the dotmatrix printer, this simple "machine" proves itself ... weird.
$endgroup$
– David Tonhofer
2 days ago














$begingroup$
Facebook and other social media are a great example of this... A lot of the consequences of their algorithms are not something that was expected by the creators (or anyone really).
$endgroup$
– aslum
2 days ago




$begingroup$
Facebook and other social media are a great example of this... A lot of the consequences of their algorithms are not something that was expected by the creators (or anyone really).
$endgroup$
– aslum
2 days ago












$begingroup$
A rather quirky individual once referred to this using a fire metaphor: "The bigger you build your bonfire of knowledge, the more darkness is revealed to your startled eye"
$endgroup$
– JacobIRR
2 days ago




$begingroup$
A rather quirky individual once referred to this using a fire metaphor: "The bigger you build your bonfire of knowledge, the more darkness is revealed to your startled eye"
$endgroup$
– JacobIRR
2 days ago










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes


















26












$begingroup$


Mathematicians and philosophers often assume that machines (and here, he probably means "computers") cannot surprise us. This is because they assume that once we learn some fact, we immediately understand every consequence of this fact. This is often a useful assumption, but it's easy to forget that it's false.




He's saying that systems with simple, finite descriptions (e.g., Turing machines) can exhibit very complicated behaviour and that this surprises some people. We can easily understand the concept of Turing machines but then we realise that they have complicated consequences, such as the undecidability of the halting problem and so on. The technical term here is that "knowledge is not closed under deduction". That is, we can know some fact $A$, but not know $B$, even though $A$ implies $B$.



Honestly, though, I'm not sure that Turing's argument is very good. Perhaps I have the benefit of writing nearly 70 years after Turing, and my understanding is that the typical mathematician knows much more about mathematical logic than they did in Turing's time. But it seems to me that mathematicians are mostly quite familiar with the idea of simple systems having complex behaviour. For example, every mathematician knows the definition of a group, which consists of just four simple axioms. But nobody – today or then – would think, "Aha. I know the four axioms, therefore I know every fact about groups." Similarly, Peano's axioms give a very short description of the natural numbers but nobody who reads them thinks "Right, I know every theorem about the natural numbers, now. Let's move on to something else."






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 16




    $begingroup$
    Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
    $endgroup$
    – BurnsBA
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    2 days ago








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 11




    $begingroup$
    Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
    $endgroup$
    – Derek Elkins
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    It is the absence of epistemic closure.
    $endgroup$
    – Dan D.
    2 days ago



















17












$begingroup$

Just an example - given chess rules, anyone should immediately figure the best strategy to play chess.



Of course, it doesn't work. Even people aren't equal, and computers may outperform us due to their better abilities to make conclusions from the facts.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
    $endgroup$
    – leftaroundabout
    yesterday






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    20 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
    $endgroup$
    – copper.hat
    37 mins ago



















8












$begingroup$

People might assume that if I write a program, and I understand the algorithm completely, and there are no bugs, then I should know what the output of that program would be, and that it should not surprise me.



Turing says (and I agree) that this is not the case: The output can be surprising. The solution to a travelling salesman problem can be surprising. The best way to build a full adder can be surprising. The best move in a chess game can be surprising.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
    $endgroup$
    – Discrete lizard
    2 days ago



















8












$begingroup$

This is the idea of emergence, which is when complex behavior of a result results from the interaction of relatively simple rules. There are lots of examples of this in nature, as that link points out. Insect colonies, bird flocks, schools of fish, and of course, consciousness. In a flock of birds or school of fish, each individual in the swam is only making decisions based on the others immediately surrounding them, but when you put a bunch of those individuals together all following those rules, you start to see more coordinated behavior than you'd expect without a higher level plan. If you go on Youtube and watch demonstrations of robot swarms, you see that they all avoid hitting each other and work in unison. Surprisingly this doesn't need to be accomplished by having a single central computer coordinate the behavior of each individual robot but can instead be done using swarm robotics where, like the insects or the birds or the fish, each robot is making local decisions which leads to emergent coordination.



Another interesting demonstration of emergent behavior is Conway's Game of Life. The rules for the game are extremely simple, but can lead to very fascinating results



A tempting argument against the ability of computers to gain human-intelligence is to say that since they can only do precisely what they're programmed to do, they must only exhibit the intelligence that we program them with. If this were true, then we would also not expect the relatively simple behavior of neurons to give rise to human intelligence. Yet as far as we can tell, this IS the case and consciousness is an emergent property of neural processing. I'm sure Turing would have loved to see what's become possible today with the use of artificial neural networks






share|cite|improve this answer










New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
    $endgroup$
    – smwikipedia
    yesterday












protected by Gilles yesterday



Thank you for your interest in this question.
Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).



Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?














4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes








4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









26












$begingroup$


Mathematicians and philosophers often assume that machines (and here, he probably means "computers") cannot surprise us. This is because they assume that once we learn some fact, we immediately understand every consequence of this fact. This is often a useful assumption, but it's easy to forget that it's false.




He's saying that systems with simple, finite descriptions (e.g., Turing machines) can exhibit very complicated behaviour and that this surprises some people. We can easily understand the concept of Turing machines but then we realise that they have complicated consequences, such as the undecidability of the halting problem and so on. The technical term here is that "knowledge is not closed under deduction". That is, we can know some fact $A$, but not know $B$, even though $A$ implies $B$.



Honestly, though, I'm not sure that Turing's argument is very good. Perhaps I have the benefit of writing nearly 70 years after Turing, and my understanding is that the typical mathematician knows much more about mathematical logic than they did in Turing's time. But it seems to me that mathematicians are mostly quite familiar with the idea of simple systems having complex behaviour. For example, every mathematician knows the definition of a group, which consists of just four simple axioms. But nobody – today or then – would think, "Aha. I know the four axioms, therefore I know every fact about groups." Similarly, Peano's axioms give a very short description of the natural numbers but nobody who reads them thinks "Right, I know every theorem about the natural numbers, now. Let's move on to something else."






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 16




    $begingroup$
    Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
    $endgroup$
    – BurnsBA
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    2 days ago








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 11




    $begingroup$
    Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
    $endgroup$
    – Derek Elkins
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    It is the absence of epistemic closure.
    $endgroup$
    – Dan D.
    2 days ago
















26












$begingroup$


Mathematicians and philosophers often assume that machines (and here, he probably means "computers") cannot surprise us. This is because they assume that once we learn some fact, we immediately understand every consequence of this fact. This is often a useful assumption, but it's easy to forget that it's false.




He's saying that systems with simple, finite descriptions (e.g., Turing machines) can exhibit very complicated behaviour and that this surprises some people. We can easily understand the concept of Turing machines but then we realise that they have complicated consequences, such as the undecidability of the halting problem and so on. The technical term here is that "knowledge is not closed under deduction". That is, we can know some fact $A$, but not know $B$, even though $A$ implies $B$.



Honestly, though, I'm not sure that Turing's argument is very good. Perhaps I have the benefit of writing nearly 70 years after Turing, and my understanding is that the typical mathematician knows much more about mathematical logic than they did in Turing's time. But it seems to me that mathematicians are mostly quite familiar with the idea of simple systems having complex behaviour. For example, every mathematician knows the definition of a group, which consists of just four simple axioms. But nobody – today or then – would think, "Aha. I know the four axioms, therefore I know every fact about groups." Similarly, Peano's axioms give a very short description of the natural numbers but nobody who reads them thinks "Right, I know every theorem about the natural numbers, now. Let's move on to something else."






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 16




    $begingroup$
    Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
    $endgroup$
    – BurnsBA
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    2 days ago








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 11




    $begingroup$
    Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
    $endgroup$
    – Derek Elkins
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    It is the absence of epistemic closure.
    $endgroup$
    – Dan D.
    2 days ago














26












26








26





$begingroup$


Mathematicians and philosophers often assume that machines (and here, he probably means "computers") cannot surprise us. This is because they assume that once we learn some fact, we immediately understand every consequence of this fact. This is often a useful assumption, but it's easy to forget that it's false.




He's saying that systems with simple, finite descriptions (e.g., Turing machines) can exhibit very complicated behaviour and that this surprises some people. We can easily understand the concept of Turing machines but then we realise that they have complicated consequences, such as the undecidability of the halting problem and so on. The technical term here is that "knowledge is not closed under deduction". That is, we can know some fact $A$, but not know $B$, even though $A$ implies $B$.



Honestly, though, I'm not sure that Turing's argument is very good. Perhaps I have the benefit of writing nearly 70 years after Turing, and my understanding is that the typical mathematician knows much more about mathematical logic than they did in Turing's time. But it seems to me that mathematicians are mostly quite familiar with the idea of simple systems having complex behaviour. For example, every mathematician knows the definition of a group, which consists of just four simple axioms. But nobody – today or then – would think, "Aha. I know the four axioms, therefore I know every fact about groups." Similarly, Peano's axioms give a very short description of the natural numbers but nobody who reads them thinks "Right, I know every theorem about the natural numbers, now. Let's move on to something else."






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$




Mathematicians and philosophers often assume that machines (and here, he probably means "computers") cannot surprise us. This is because they assume that once we learn some fact, we immediately understand every consequence of this fact. This is often a useful assumption, but it's easy to forget that it's false.




He's saying that systems with simple, finite descriptions (e.g., Turing machines) can exhibit very complicated behaviour and that this surprises some people. We can easily understand the concept of Turing machines but then we realise that they have complicated consequences, such as the undecidability of the halting problem and so on. The technical term here is that "knowledge is not closed under deduction". That is, we can know some fact $A$, but not know $B$, even though $A$ implies $B$.



Honestly, though, I'm not sure that Turing's argument is very good. Perhaps I have the benefit of writing nearly 70 years after Turing, and my understanding is that the typical mathematician knows much more about mathematical logic than they did in Turing's time. But it seems to me that mathematicians are mostly quite familiar with the idea of simple systems having complex behaviour. For example, every mathematician knows the definition of a group, which consists of just four simple axioms. But nobody – today or then – would think, "Aha. I know the four axioms, therefore I know every fact about groups." Similarly, Peano's axioms give a very short description of the natural numbers but nobody who reads them thinks "Right, I know every theorem about the natural numbers, now. Let's move on to something else."







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 2 days ago

























answered 2 days ago









David RicherbyDavid Richerby

70.8k16108198




70.8k16108198








  • 16




    $begingroup$
    Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
    $endgroup$
    – BurnsBA
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    2 days ago








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 11




    $begingroup$
    Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
    $endgroup$
    – Derek Elkins
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    It is the absence of epistemic closure.
    $endgroup$
    – Dan D.
    2 days ago














  • 16




    $begingroup$
    Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
    $endgroup$
    – BurnsBA
    2 days ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
    $endgroup$
    – alephzero
    2 days ago








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
    $endgroup$
    – David Richerby
    2 days ago






  • 11




    $begingroup$
    Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
    $endgroup$
    – Derek Elkins
    2 days ago












  • $begingroup$
    It is the absence of epistemic closure.
    $endgroup$
    – Dan D.
    2 days ago








16




16




$begingroup$
Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
$endgroup$
– BurnsBA
2 days ago




$begingroup$
Historically, the early 20th century had a strong academic belief in "solving" mathematics. E.g., Hilbert's program, and Whitehead+Russel's Principia Mathematica. Godel's work resolved that quest negatively, but I imagine it took some time for academia to fully embrace this notion; even fully acknowledging the correctness of Godel, people would still remember the grand ideas of Hilbert. I think Turing writing only two decades after Godel would be addressing his audience with this context in mind.
$endgroup$
– BurnsBA
2 days ago




5




5




$begingroup$
I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
$endgroup$
– alephzero
2 days ago






$begingroup$
I would question whether most mathematicians know "much more about mathematical logic" than Turing did. But it is obvious that almost all contemporary humans have vastly more practical experience of what machines (and particularly computers) can do than he did.
$endgroup$
– alephzero
2 days ago






3




3




$begingroup$
@alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
$endgroup$
– David Richerby
2 days ago




$begingroup$
@alephzero That's not what I said! I said that the average mathematician today knows more about mathematical logic than the average mathematician during Turing's time.
$endgroup$
– David Richerby
2 days ago




11




11




$begingroup$
Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
2 days ago






$begingroup$
Your argument seems to be not that Turing's argument isn't good, but that it is unnecessary or directed at a strawman. I strongly suspect Turing had real people make arguments like this to him, so I don't think he's making a strawman out of nothing. As Discrete lizard states in a comment, Turing is only saying that a particular argument against machines surprising us is bad. Your answer just says that that this argument is bad has become even more obvious over time. That said, people (though usually not experts) still make arguments in this vein today.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
2 days ago














$begingroup$
It is the absence of epistemic closure.
$endgroup$
– Dan D.
2 days ago




$begingroup$
It is the absence of epistemic closure.
$endgroup$
– Dan D.
2 days ago











17












$begingroup$

Just an example - given chess rules, anyone should immediately figure the best strategy to play chess.



Of course, it doesn't work. Even people aren't equal, and computers may outperform us due to their better abilities to make conclusions from the facts.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
    $endgroup$
    – leftaroundabout
    yesterday






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    20 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
    $endgroup$
    – copper.hat
    37 mins ago
















17












$begingroup$

Just an example - given chess rules, anyone should immediately figure the best strategy to play chess.



Of course, it doesn't work. Even people aren't equal, and computers may outperform us due to their better abilities to make conclusions from the facts.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
    $endgroup$
    – leftaroundabout
    yesterday






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    20 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
    $endgroup$
    – copper.hat
    37 mins ago














17












17








17





$begingroup$

Just an example - given chess rules, anyone should immediately figure the best strategy to play chess.



Of course, it doesn't work. Even people aren't equal, and computers may outperform us due to their better abilities to make conclusions from the facts.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



Just an example - given chess rules, anyone should immediately figure the best strategy to play chess.



Of course, it doesn't work. Even people aren't equal, and computers may outperform us due to their better abilities to make conclusions from the facts.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered 2 days ago









BulatBulat

1,042612




1,042612












  • $begingroup$
    Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
    $endgroup$
    – leftaroundabout
    yesterday






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    20 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
    $endgroup$
    – copper.hat
    37 mins ago


















  • $begingroup$
    Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
    $endgroup$
    – leftaroundabout
    yesterday






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
    $endgroup$
    – Bulat
    20 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
    $endgroup$
    – copper.hat
    37 mins ago
















$begingroup$
Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
$endgroup$
– leftaroundabout
yesterday




$begingroup$
Not sure that's a good example. People do readily come up with chess strategies, as soon as they properly grasp the rules, and though these strategies are obviously flawed and useless against more experienced players and modern engines, they would have been good enough against early computer chess engines.
$endgroup$
– leftaroundabout
yesterday




1




1




$begingroup$
My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
$endgroup$
– Bulat
20 hours ago




$begingroup$
My point exactly that not only people are different, but computers are different too, so stupid computers of Turing era doesn't mean that they always will be stupid. You may need to know, though, that Turing died long before computers started playing chess.
$endgroup$
– Bulat
20 hours ago












$begingroup$
I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
37 mins ago




$begingroup$
I think this is a good example, and captures the essence of Turing's paragraph.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
37 mins ago











8












$begingroup$

People might assume that if I write a program, and I understand the algorithm completely, and there are no bugs, then I should know what the output of that program would be, and that it should not surprise me.



Turing says (and I agree) that this is not the case: The output can be surprising. The solution to a travelling salesman problem can be surprising. The best way to build a full adder can be surprising. The best move in a chess game can be surprising.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
    $endgroup$
    – Discrete lizard
    2 days ago
















8












$begingroup$

People might assume that if I write a program, and I understand the algorithm completely, and there are no bugs, then I should know what the output of that program would be, and that it should not surprise me.



Turing says (and I agree) that this is not the case: The output can be surprising. The solution to a travelling salesman problem can be surprising. The best way to build a full adder can be surprising. The best move in a chess game can be surprising.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
    $endgroup$
    – Discrete lizard
    2 days ago














8












8








8





$begingroup$

People might assume that if I write a program, and I understand the algorithm completely, and there are no bugs, then I should know what the output of that program would be, and that it should not surprise me.



Turing says (and I agree) that this is not the case: The output can be surprising. The solution to a travelling salesman problem can be surprising. The best way to build a full adder can be surprising. The best move in a chess game can be surprising.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



People might assume that if I write a program, and I understand the algorithm completely, and there are no bugs, then I should know what the output of that program would be, and that it should not surprise me.



Turing says (and I agree) that this is not the case: The output can be surprising. The solution to a travelling salesman problem can be surprising. The best way to build a full adder can be surprising. The best move in a chess game can be surprising.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered 2 days ago









gnasher729gnasher729

12.1k1318




12.1k1318












  • $begingroup$
    This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
    $endgroup$
    – Discrete lizard
    2 days ago


















  • $begingroup$
    This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
    $endgroup$
    – Discrete lizard
    2 days ago
















$begingroup$
This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
$endgroup$
– Discrete lizard
2 days ago




$begingroup$
This does explain why computers could be surprising which is the first half of the quote, but you do not address the part of the quote that explains why a particular argument that machines cannot surprise is fallacious.
$endgroup$
– Discrete lizard
2 days ago











8












$begingroup$

This is the idea of emergence, which is when complex behavior of a result results from the interaction of relatively simple rules. There are lots of examples of this in nature, as that link points out. Insect colonies, bird flocks, schools of fish, and of course, consciousness. In a flock of birds or school of fish, each individual in the swam is only making decisions based on the others immediately surrounding them, but when you put a bunch of those individuals together all following those rules, you start to see more coordinated behavior than you'd expect without a higher level plan. If you go on Youtube and watch demonstrations of robot swarms, you see that they all avoid hitting each other and work in unison. Surprisingly this doesn't need to be accomplished by having a single central computer coordinate the behavior of each individual robot but can instead be done using swarm robotics where, like the insects or the birds or the fish, each robot is making local decisions which leads to emergent coordination.



Another interesting demonstration of emergent behavior is Conway's Game of Life. The rules for the game are extremely simple, but can lead to very fascinating results



A tempting argument against the ability of computers to gain human-intelligence is to say that since they can only do precisely what they're programmed to do, they must only exhibit the intelligence that we program them with. If this were true, then we would also not expect the relatively simple behavior of neurons to give rise to human intelligence. Yet as far as we can tell, this IS the case and consciousness is an emergent property of neural processing. I'm sure Turing would have loved to see what's become possible today with the use of artificial neural networks






share|cite|improve this answer










New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
    $endgroup$
    – smwikipedia
    yesterday


















8












$begingroup$

This is the idea of emergence, which is when complex behavior of a result results from the interaction of relatively simple rules. There are lots of examples of this in nature, as that link points out. Insect colonies, bird flocks, schools of fish, and of course, consciousness. In a flock of birds or school of fish, each individual in the swam is only making decisions based on the others immediately surrounding them, but when you put a bunch of those individuals together all following those rules, you start to see more coordinated behavior than you'd expect without a higher level plan. If you go on Youtube and watch demonstrations of robot swarms, you see that they all avoid hitting each other and work in unison. Surprisingly this doesn't need to be accomplished by having a single central computer coordinate the behavior of each individual robot but can instead be done using swarm robotics where, like the insects or the birds or the fish, each robot is making local decisions which leads to emergent coordination.



Another interesting demonstration of emergent behavior is Conway's Game of Life. The rules for the game are extremely simple, but can lead to very fascinating results



A tempting argument against the ability of computers to gain human-intelligence is to say that since they can only do precisely what they're programmed to do, they must only exhibit the intelligence that we program them with. If this were true, then we would also not expect the relatively simple behavior of neurons to give rise to human intelligence. Yet as far as we can tell, this IS the case and consciousness is an emergent property of neural processing. I'm sure Turing would have loved to see what's become possible today with the use of artificial neural networks






share|cite|improve this answer










New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
    $endgroup$
    – smwikipedia
    yesterday
















8












8








8





$begingroup$

This is the idea of emergence, which is when complex behavior of a result results from the interaction of relatively simple rules. There are lots of examples of this in nature, as that link points out. Insect colonies, bird flocks, schools of fish, and of course, consciousness. In a flock of birds or school of fish, each individual in the swam is only making decisions based on the others immediately surrounding them, but when you put a bunch of those individuals together all following those rules, you start to see more coordinated behavior than you'd expect without a higher level plan. If you go on Youtube and watch demonstrations of robot swarms, you see that they all avoid hitting each other and work in unison. Surprisingly this doesn't need to be accomplished by having a single central computer coordinate the behavior of each individual robot but can instead be done using swarm robotics where, like the insects or the birds or the fish, each robot is making local decisions which leads to emergent coordination.



Another interesting demonstration of emergent behavior is Conway's Game of Life. The rules for the game are extremely simple, but can lead to very fascinating results



A tempting argument against the ability of computers to gain human-intelligence is to say that since they can only do precisely what they're programmed to do, they must only exhibit the intelligence that we program them with. If this were true, then we would also not expect the relatively simple behavior of neurons to give rise to human intelligence. Yet as far as we can tell, this IS the case and consciousness is an emergent property of neural processing. I'm sure Turing would have loved to see what's become possible today with the use of artificial neural networks






share|cite|improve this answer










New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$



This is the idea of emergence, which is when complex behavior of a result results from the interaction of relatively simple rules. There are lots of examples of this in nature, as that link points out. Insect colonies, bird flocks, schools of fish, and of course, consciousness. In a flock of birds or school of fish, each individual in the swam is only making decisions based on the others immediately surrounding them, but when you put a bunch of those individuals together all following those rules, you start to see more coordinated behavior than you'd expect without a higher level plan. If you go on Youtube and watch demonstrations of robot swarms, you see that they all avoid hitting each other and work in unison. Surprisingly this doesn't need to be accomplished by having a single central computer coordinate the behavior of each individual robot but can instead be done using swarm robotics where, like the insects or the birds or the fish, each robot is making local decisions which leads to emergent coordination.



Another interesting demonstration of emergent behavior is Conway's Game of Life. The rules for the game are extremely simple, but can lead to very fascinating results



A tempting argument against the ability of computers to gain human-intelligence is to say that since they can only do precisely what they're programmed to do, they must only exhibit the intelligence that we program them with. If this were true, then we would also not expect the relatively simple behavior of neurons to give rise to human intelligence. Yet as far as we can tell, this IS the case and consciousness is an emergent property of neural processing. I'm sure Turing would have loved to see what's become possible today with the use of artificial neural networks







share|cite|improve this answer










New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 2 days ago





















New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









answered 2 days ago









mowwwalkermowwwalker

1892




1892




New contributor




mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






mowwwalker is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
    $endgroup$
    – smwikipedia
    yesterday
















  • 2




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
    $endgroup$
    – smwikipedia
    yesterday










2




2




$begingroup$
Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
$endgroup$
– smwikipedia
yesterday






$begingroup$
Thanks for mentioning the emergence. You add some optimism to my pessimism about A.I through computation.
$endgroup$
– smwikipedia
yesterday







protected by Gilles yesterday



Thank you for your interest in this question.
Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).



Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?



Popular posts from this blog

Couldn't open a raw socket. Error: Permission denied (13) (nmap)Is it possible to run networking commands...

VNC viewer RFB protocol error: bad desktop size 0x0I Cannot Type the Key 'd' (lowercase) in VNC Viewer...

Why not use the yoke to control yaw, as well as pitch and roll? Announcing the arrival of...