Coin Game with infinite paradox Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar...
Why do people think Winterfell crypts is the safest place for women, children & old people?
Why is one lightbulb in a string illuminated?
Salesforce - multiple pre production environments
How to produce a PS1 prompt in bash or ksh93 similar to tcsh
Converting a text document with special format to Pandas DataFrame
Do chord progressions usually move by fifths?
/bin/ls sorts differently than just ls
lm and glm function in R
Raising a bilingual kid. When should we introduce the majority language?
Recursive calls to a function - why is the address of the parameter passed to it lowering with each call?
2 sample t test for sample sizes - 30,000 and 150,000
How to get a single big right brace?
Pointing to problems without suggesting solutions
Protagonist's race is hidden - should I reveal it?
A German immigrant ancestor has a "Registration Affidavit of Alien Enemy" on file. What does that mean exactly?
What were wait-states, and why was it only an issue for PCs?
Compiling and throwing simple dynamic exceptions at runtime for JVM
How to mute a string and play another at the same time
Can I ask an author to send me his ebook?
Does the Pact of the Blade warlock feature allow me to customize the properties of the pact weapon I create?
Can I take recommendation from someone I met at a conference?
Will I be more secure with my own router behind my ISP's router?
Who's this lady in the war room?
Kepler's 3rd law: ratios don't fit data
Coin Game with infinite paradox
Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara
Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern)Flip a Fair CoinAnother probabilistic coin puzzleLeft coin, Right coin, Last coin- A fair versionCoin Flipping Game with the DevilCoin division puzzleEccentric Millionaire Probability ParadoxWhat is the value of this other coin flipping game?The asymmetric coin gameFind Coin's unfairness with only 4 tossesThe Monster and the Chessboard
$begingroup$
Here’s the puzzle/problem:
Let’s presume we are best friends. I own the house next to you. I make a gaming proposition along the following lines:
You throw a coin over and over again. So long as it comes up heads, you keep throwing. When it comes up tails you stop and I pay you $$$ — depending on how many heads you threw.
If you threw a tails to start, you get $0.
If you threw a heads then a tails, you get $1.
If you threw 2 heads then a tails, you get $2.
If you threw 3 heads, you get $4.
If you threw 4 heads, you get $8.
If you threw 5 heads, you get $16.
And on and on. The payoff doubles everytime you add an extra heads.
How much will you pay me to play this game (once)?
Note: This is not a loophole question, you will know when you have the right answer.
logical-deduction probability coins
New contributor
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here’s the puzzle/problem:
Let’s presume we are best friends. I own the house next to you. I make a gaming proposition along the following lines:
You throw a coin over and over again. So long as it comes up heads, you keep throwing. When it comes up tails you stop and I pay you $$$ — depending on how many heads you threw.
If you threw a tails to start, you get $0.
If you threw a heads then a tails, you get $1.
If you threw 2 heads then a tails, you get $2.
If you threw 3 heads, you get $4.
If you threw 4 heads, you get $8.
If you threw 5 heads, you get $16.
And on and on. The payoff doubles everytime you add an extra heads.
How much will you pay me to play this game (once)?
Note: This is not a loophole question, you will know when you have the right answer.
logical-deduction probability coins
New contributor
$endgroup$
4
$begingroup$
This is known as St Petersburg paradox.en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/St._Petersburg_paradox
$endgroup$
– Tojrah
9 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here’s the puzzle/problem:
Let’s presume we are best friends. I own the house next to you. I make a gaming proposition along the following lines:
You throw a coin over and over again. So long as it comes up heads, you keep throwing. When it comes up tails you stop and I pay you $$$ — depending on how many heads you threw.
If you threw a tails to start, you get $0.
If you threw a heads then a tails, you get $1.
If you threw 2 heads then a tails, you get $2.
If you threw 3 heads, you get $4.
If you threw 4 heads, you get $8.
If you threw 5 heads, you get $16.
And on and on. The payoff doubles everytime you add an extra heads.
How much will you pay me to play this game (once)?
Note: This is not a loophole question, you will know when you have the right answer.
logical-deduction probability coins
New contributor
$endgroup$
Here’s the puzzle/problem:
Let’s presume we are best friends. I own the house next to you. I make a gaming proposition along the following lines:
You throw a coin over and over again. So long as it comes up heads, you keep throwing. When it comes up tails you stop and I pay you $$$ — depending on how many heads you threw.
If you threw a tails to start, you get $0.
If you threw a heads then a tails, you get $1.
If you threw 2 heads then a tails, you get $2.
If you threw 3 heads, you get $4.
If you threw 4 heads, you get $8.
If you threw 5 heads, you get $16.
And on and on. The payoff doubles everytime you add an extra heads.
How much will you pay me to play this game (once)?
Note: This is not a loophole question, you will know when you have the right answer.
logical-deduction probability coins
logical-deduction probability coins
New contributor
New contributor
New contributor
asked 9 hours ago
SpqrTiangSpqrTiang
361
361
New contributor
New contributor
4
$begingroup$
This is known as St Petersburg paradox.en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/St._Petersburg_paradox
$endgroup$
– Tojrah
9 hours ago
add a comment |
4
$begingroup$
This is known as St Petersburg paradox.en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/St._Petersburg_paradox
$endgroup$
– Tojrah
9 hours ago
4
4
$begingroup$
This is known as St Petersburg paradox.en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/St._Petersburg_paradox
$endgroup$
– Tojrah
9 hours ago
$begingroup$
This is known as St Petersburg paradox.en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/St._Petersburg_paradox
$endgroup$
– Tojrah
9 hours ago
add a comment |
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
OK, let's actually take this seriously. As others have said, this is the so-called St Petersburg paradox, and the reason it isn't really much of a paradox is that (1) an extra dollar matters much less when you already have a lot of money and (2) our counterparty may not actually pay up. So let's model that.
The simplest somewhat-plausible way to handle #1 is to suppose that the value to you of your material assets is roughly proportional to the logarithm of their total value or, equivalently, that the value to you of your "next" dollar is roughly inversely proportional to your current net wealth. (There's some evidence that it actually grows a bit slower than that, but it'll do).
The way I'll handle #2 is to suppose that the probability that you pay up when I win $$X$ in the game is roughly proportional to $frac a{a+X}$ where $a$ is a fairly large number; so when $X$ is small you almost certainly pay and when $X$ is very large you almost certainly don't. (We should expect $a$ to be of the same order of magnitude as your net wealth in dollars; it's the size of payoff at which I think it's equally likely that you will or won't pay up.)
Then, if my net wealth before playing the game is $$w$ and your pay-or-don't parameter is $$a$, the "correct" price $$p$ is such that
$$frac12logfrac{w-p}w+sum_{k=0}^{infty}frac1{2^{k+2}}frac{a}{a+2^k}logfrac{w-p+2^k}w=0.$$
This isn't the sort of thing we should expect to be able to solve analytically; so far as I know there is no nice closed form for that sum. But we can do it numerically. Here are some specific results. (I cannot guarantee that I haven't messed up the calculations, though the numbers seem plausible enough to me.)
- Suppose your $a$ parameter is ($)1000000, so that your probability of paying up has reduced to 1/2 by the time you owe me a megabuck. And suppose my own net wealth happens also to be one megabuck. Then I should be willing to pay about $4.87.
- Suppose my net wealth remains at $1M but now $a$ is $$10^9$; even once you owe me a billion dollars you might well pay up. Then the amount I'm willing to pay increases to about ... $5.46.
- Suppose you remain a billionaire but I am much poorer, having only $1000 to my name. Then the amount I'm willing to pay goes down to $2.98. (It goes down because the poorer I am, the faster the value-to-me of a dollar decreases as I get more.)
- Suppose we're both poor, so I'm at $1000 and your $a$ parameter is the same. Then I am willing to pay about $2.39.
- Suppose I am a billionaire and you have infinitely much money. Then I am willing to pay about $12.80.
So I'm fairly comfortable answering the original question as follows: I am willing to pay somewhere between about $2 and about $13, depending on how wealthy we both are and how much I trust you to pay up even if doing so is painful for you.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This gambling problem is the famous St. Petersburg paradox. It is a paradox because
the wager has infinite expected value regardless of the amount paid to play. A rational agent should pay
any amount of money to play this game, and over many rounds of the game, they can expect to make a profit.
The one issue with this theoretical result is that it requires no upper limit on the possible winnings - if you make it through enough coin flips, you can win more money than the combined wealth of everyone on the planet. If we limit the lottery to a maximum payout of the world GDP (~$55 trillion), the expected value of the lottery is
around $45.
This analysis also assumes that each dollar won has equal utility, which is a measure of what a dollar means to you personally. Utility of money tends to flatten out for large amounts - a $10 million, for example, is a life-changing amount of money, but the next $10 million won't have as big an impact on your life as the first $10 million. So, $20 million is not really "worth" twice as much as $10 million. The "infinite wager" solution to the St. Petersburg paradox assumes constant utility of money, even though that's not a realistic model of how people behave.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I would pay you
All my money, and then be sad when I lost it all on the first flip
because
Let the amount I pay you be represented as C. After paying C, you have a 1/2 chance of winning 0, a 1/4 chance of winning 1, a 1/8 chance of winning 2, a 1/16 chance of winning 4 etc. Your expected payout would be $$-C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{2^{i+2}}2^i = -C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{4} = -C + infty$$ Theoretically if you played forever and ever, you would profit no matter how much you paid per game. Realistically, you would probably not profit no matter how much you paid.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
There are several nuances to this question. First of all, it asks how much you are willing to pay, not what price is fair. Second, you have to understand, that even if a game is fair, that does not mean that It is reasonable to play it.
For example, if someone offers me a one in a million chance to win a million dollars for 1, I will take it. It seems reasonable. But if someone offered me a one in a million chance to win a billion dollars for 1000, I would not. What’s the difference? I am willing to lose a dollar for a small chance at success, but I am not willing to lose a thousand dollars for that same small chance, even if the reward is adjusted accordingly.
You have to factor in how much money you are willing to lose if the game does not go your way, especially if you only play once.
Since there is a 50% chance to lose your whole wager, the question becomes how much is the reward, but also how much are you willing to lose for it? If the reward was a million dollars, I would not wager 500,000 for a 50% chance to lose it, even if that is a “fair” game.
Realistically, I know the chance of getting a long streak of heads in a row is very low. Even though in 100 coin flips it’s not uncommon to have several streaks of 5 to 7 heads or tails in a row, playing the game only once means that the law of large numbers doesn’t apply.
For these reasons, I would not wager more than $1 for this game, because I don’t expect to see more than 3 heads in a row.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I will pay you
One dollar
to play this game, because
The amount you pay me has no bearing on what I pay you.
If there was a single throw there would be 50-50 chance of getting my dollar back.
But the game can go on, so there is better than 50-50 of getting my dollar back.
Your bankroll is the limit — your house against my $1.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To play once I would pay:
50 cents, since it is a doubling game and one heads is a dollar.
New contributor
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "559"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: false,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: null,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
SpqrTiang is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fpuzzling.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f82060%2fcoin-game-with-infinite-paradox%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
OK, let's actually take this seriously. As others have said, this is the so-called St Petersburg paradox, and the reason it isn't really much of a paradox is that (1) an extra dollar matters much less when you already have a lot of money and (2) our counterparty may not actually pay up. So let's model that.
The simplest somewhat-plausible way to handle #1 is to suppose that the value to you of your material assets is roughly proportional to the logarithm of their total value or, equivalently, that the value to you of your "next" dollar is roughly inversely proportional to your current net wealth. (There's some evidence that it actually grows a bit slower than that, but it'll do).
The way I'll handle #2 is to suppose that the probability that you pay up when I win $$X$ in the game is roughly proportional to $frac a{a+X}$ where $a$ is a fairly large number; so when $X$ is small you almost certainly pay and when $X$ is very large you almost certainly don't. (We should expect $a$ to be of the same order of magnitude as your net wealth in dollars; it's the size of payoff at which I think it's equally likely that you will or won't pay up.)
Then, if my net wealth before playing the game is $$w$ and your pay-or-don't parameter is $$a$, the "correct" price $$p$ is such that
$$frac12logfrac{w-p}w+sum_{k=0}^{infty}frac1{2^{k+2}}frac{a}{a+2^k}logfrac{w-p+2^k}w=0.$$
This isn't the sort of thing we should expect to be able to solve analytically; so far as I know there is no nice closed form for that sum. But we can do it numerically. Here are some specific results. (I cannot guarantee that I haven't messed up the calculations, though the numbers seem plausible enough to me.)
- Suppose your $a$ parameter is ($)1000000, so that your probability of paying up has reduced to 1/2 by the time you owe me a megabuck. And suppose my own net wealth happens also to be one megabuck. Then I should be willing to pay about $4.87.
- Suppose my net wealth remains at $1M but now $a$ is $$10^9$; even once you owe me a billion dollars you might well pay up. Then the amount I'm willing to pay increases to about ... $5.46.
- Suppose you remain a billionaire but I am much poorer, having only $1000 to my name. Then the amount I'm willing to pay goes down to $2.98. (It goes down because the poorer I am, the faster the value-to-me of a dollar decreases as I get more.)
- Suppose we're both poor, so I'm at $1000 and your $a$ parameter is the same. Then I am willing to pay about $2.39.
- Suppose I am a billionaire and you have infinitely much money. Then I am willing to pay about $12.80.
So I'm fairly comfortable answering the original question as follows: I am willing to pay somewhere between about $2 and about $13, depending on how wealthy we both are and how much I trust you to pay up even if doing so is painful for you.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
OK, let's actually take this seriously. As others have said, this is the so-called St Petersburg paradox, and the reason it isn't really much of a paradox is that (1) an extra dollar matters much less when you already have a lot of money and (2) our counterparty may not actually pay up. So let's model that.
The simplest somewhat-plausible way to handle #1 is to suppose that the value to you of your material assets is roughly proportional to the logarithm of their total value or, equivalently, that the value to you of your "next" dollar is roughly inversely proportional to your current net wealth. (There's some evidence that it actually grows a bit slower than that, but it'll do).
The way I'll handle #2 is to suppose that the probability that you pay up when I win $$X$ in the game is roughly proportional to $frac a{a+X}$ where $a$ is a fairly large number; so when $X$ is small you almost certainly pay and when $X$ is very large you almost certainly don't. (We should expect $a$ to be of the same order of magnitude as your net wealth in dollars; it's the size of payoff at which I think it's equally likely that you will or won't pay up.)
Then, if my net wealth before playing the game is $$w$ and your pay-or-don't parameter is $$a$, the "correct" price $$p$ is such that
$$frac12logfrac{w-p}w+sum_{k=0}^{infty}frac1{2^{k+2}}frac{a}{a+2^k}logfrac{w-p+2^k}w=0.$$
This isn't the sort of thing we should expect to be able to solve analytically; so far as I know there is no nice closed form for that sum. But we can do it numerically. Here are some specific results. (I cannot guarantee that I haven't messed up the calculations, though the numbers seem plausible enough to me.)
- Suppose your $a$ parameter is ($)1000000, so that your probability of paying up has reduced to 1/2 by the time you owe me a megabuck. And suppose my own net wealth happens also to be one megabuck. Then I should be willing to pay about $4.87.
- Suppose my net wealth remains at $1M but now $a$ is $$10^9$; even once you owe me a billion dollars you might well pay up. Then the amount I'm willing to pay increases to about ... $5.46.
- Suppose you remain a billionaire but I am much poorer, having only $1000 to my name. Then the amount I'm willing to pay goes down to $2.98. (It goes down because the poorer I am, the faster the value-to-me of a dollar decreases as I get more.)
- Suppose we're both poor, so I'm at $1000 and your $a$ parameter is the same. Then I am willing to pay about $2.39.
- Suppose I am a billionaire and you have infinitely much money. Then I am willing to pay about $12.80.
So I'm fairly comfortable answering the original question as follows: I am willing to pay somewhere between about $2 and about $13, depending on how wealthy we both are and how much I trust you to pay up even if doing so is painful for you.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
OK, let's actually take this seriously. As others have said, this is the so-called St Petersburg paradox, and the reason it isn't really much of a paradox is that (1) an extra dollar matters much less when you already have a lot of money and (2) our counterparty may not actually pay up. So let's model that.
The simplest somewhat-plausible way to handle #1 is to suppose that the value to you of your material assets is roughly proportional to the logarithm of their total value or, equivalently, that the value to you of your "next" dollar is roughly inversely proportional to your current net wealth. (There's some evidence that it actually grows a bit slower than that, but it'll do).
The way I'll handle #2 is to suppose that the probability that you pay up when I win $$X$ in the game is roughly proportional to $frac a{a+X}$ where $a$ is a fairly large number; so when $X$ is small you almost certainly pay and when $X$ is very large you almost certainly don't. (We should expect $a$ to be of the same order of magnitude as your net wealth in dollars; it's the size of payoff at which I think it's equally likely that you will or won't pay up.)
Then, if my net wealth before playing the game is $$w$ and your pay-or-don't parameter is $$a$, the "correct" price $$p$ is such that
$$frac12logfrac{w-p}w+sum_{k=0}^{infty}frac1{2^{k+2}}frac{a}{a+2^k}logfrac{w-p+2^k}w=0.$$
This isn't the sort of thing we should expect to be able to solve analytically; so far as I know there is no nice closed form for that sum. But we can do it numerically. Here are some specific results. (I cannot guarantee that I haven't messed up the calculations, though the numbers seem plausible enough to me.)
- Suppose your $a$ parameter is ($)1000000, so that your probability of paying up has reduced to 1/2 by the time you owe me a megabuck. And suppose my own net wealth happens also to be one megabuck. Then I should be willing to pay about $4.87.
- Suppose my net wealth remains at $1M but now $a$ is $$10^9$; even once you owe me a billion dollars you might well pay up. Then the amount I'm willing to pay increases to about ... $5.46.
- Suppose you remain a billionaire but I am much poorer, having only $1000 to my name. Then the amount I'm willing to pay goes down to $2.98. (It goes down because the poorer I am, the faster the value-to-me of a dollar decreases as I get more.)
- Suppose we're both poor, so I'm at $1000 and your $a$ parameter is the same. Then I am willing to pay about $2.39.
- Suppose I am a billionaire and you have infinitely much money. Then I am willing to pay about $12.80.
So I'm fairly comfortable answering the original question as follows: I am willing to pay somewhere between about $2 and about $13, depending on how wealthy we both are and how much I trust you to pay up even if doing so is painful for you.
$endgroup$
OK, let's actually take this seriously. As others have said, this is the so-called St Petersburg paradox, and the reason it isn't really much of a paradox is that (1) an extra dollar matters much less when you already have a lot of money and (2) our counterparty may not actually pay up. So let's model that.
The simplest somewhat-plausible way to handle #1 is to suppose that the value to you of your material assets is roughly proportional to the logarithm of their total value or, equivalently, that the value to you of your "next" dollar is roughly inversely proportional to your current net wealth. (There's some evidence that it actually grows a bit slower than that, but it'll do).
The way I'll handle #2 is to suppose that the probability that you pay up when I win $$X$ in the game is roughly proportional to $frac a{a+X}$ where $a$ is a fairly large number; so when $X$ is small you almost certainly pay and when $X$ is very large you almost certainly don't. (We should expect $a$ to be of the same order of magnitude as your net wealth in dollars; it's the size of payoff at which I think it's equally likely that you will or won't pay up.)
Then, if my net wealth before playing the game is $$w$ and your pay-or-don't parameter is $$a$, the "correct" price $$p$ is such that
$$frac12logfrac{w-p}w+sum_{k=0}^{infty}frac1{2^{k+2}}frac{a}{a+2^k}logfrac{w-p+2^k}w=0.$$
This isn't the sort of thing we should expect to be able to solve analytically; so far as I know there is no nice closed form for that sum. But we can do it numerically. Here are some specific results. (I cannot guarantee that I haven't messed up the calculations, though the numbers seem plausible enough to me.)
- Suppose your $a$ parameter is ($)1000000, so that your probability of paying up has reduced to 1/2 by the time you owe me a megabuck. And suppose my own net wealth happens also to be one megabuck. Then I should be willing to pay about $4.87.
- Suppose my net wealth remains at $1M but now $a$ is $$10^9$; even once you owe me a billion dollars you might well pay up. Then the amount I'm willing to pay increases to about ... $5.46.
- Suppose you remain a billionaire but I am much poorer, having only $1000 to my name. Then the amount I'm willing to pay goes down to $2.98. (It goes down because the poorer I am, the faster the value-to-me of a dollar decreases as I get more.)
- Suppose we're both poor, so I'm at $1000 and your $a$ parameter is the same. Then I am willing to pay about $2.39.
- Suppose I am a billionaire and you have infinitely much money. Then I am willing to pay about $12.80.
So I'm fairly comfortable answering the original question as follows: I am willing to pay somewhere between about $2 and about $13, depending on how wealthy we both are and how much I trust you to pay up even if doing so is painful for you.
answered 7 hours ago
Gareth McCaughan♦Gareth McCaughan
68.1k3172265
68.1k3172265
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This gambling problem is the famous St. Petersburg paradox. It is a paradox because
the wager has infinite expected value regardless of the amount paid to play. A rational agent should pay
any amount of money to play this game, and over many rounds of the game, they can expect to make a profit.
The one issue with this theoretical result is that it requires no upper limit on the possible winnings - if you make it through enough coin flips, you can win more money than the combined wealth of everyone on the planet. If we limit the lottery to a maximum payout of the world GDP (~$55 trillion), the expected value of the lottery is
around $45.
This analysis also assumes that each dollar won has equal utility, which is a measure of what a dollar means to you personally. Utility of money tends to flatten out for large amounts - a $10 million, for example, is a life-changing amount of money, but the next $10 million won't have as big an impact on your life as the first $10 million. So, $20 million is not really "worth" twice as much as $10 million. The "infinite wager" solution to the St. Petersburg paradox assumes constant utility of money, even though that's not a realistic model of how people behave.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This gambling problem is the famous St. Petersburg paradox. It is a paradox because
the wager has infinite expected value regardless of the amount paid to play. A rational agent should pay
any amount of money to play this game, and over many rounds of the game, they can expect to make a profit.
The one issue with this theoretical result is that it requires no upper limit on the possible winnings - if you make it through enough coin flips, you can win more money than the combined wealth of everyone on the planet. If we limit the lottery to a maximum payout of the world GDP (~$55 trillion), the expected value of the lottery is
around $45.
This analysis also assumes that each dollar won has equal utility, which is a measure of what a dollar means to you personally. Utility of money tends to flatten out for large amounts - a $10 million, for example, is a life-changing amount of money, but the next $10 million won't have as big an impact on your life as the first $10 million. So, $20 million is not really "worth" twice as much as $10 million. The "infinite wager" solution to the St. Petersburg paradox assumes constant utility of money, even though that's not a realistic model of how people behave.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This gambling problem is the famous St. Petersburg paradox. It is a paradox because
the wager has infinite expected value regardless of the amount paid to play. A rational agent should pay
any amount of money to play this game, and over many rounds of the game, they can expect to make a profit.
The one issue with this theoretical result is that it requires no upper limit on the possible winnings - if you make it through enough coin flips, you can win more money than the combined wealth of everyone on the planet. If we limit the lottery to a maximum payout of the world GDP (~$55 trillion), the expected value of the lottery is
around $45.
This analysis also assumes that each dollar won has equal utility, which is a measure of what a dollar means to you personally. Utility of money tends to flatten out for large amounts - a $10 million, for example, is a life-changing amount of money, but the next $10 million won't have as big an impact on your life as the first $10 million. So, $20 million is not really "worth" twice as much as $10 million. The "infinite wager" solution to the St. Petersburg paradox assumes constant utility of money, even though that's not a realistic model of how people behave.
$endgroup$
This gambling problem is the famous St. Petersburg paradox. It is a paradox because
the wager has infinite expected value regardless of the amount paid to play. A rational agent should pay
any amount of money to play this game, and over many rounds of the game, they can expect to make a profit.
The one issue with this theoretical result is that it requires no upper limit on the possible winnings - if you make it through enough coin flips, you can win more money than the combined wealth of everyone on the planet. If we limit the lottery to a maximum payout of the world GDP (~$55 trillion), the expected value of the lottery is
around $45.
This analysis also assumes that each dollar won has equal utility, which is a measure of what a dollar means to you personally. Utility of money tends to flatten out for large amounts - a $10 million, for example, is a life-changing amount of money, but the next $10 million won't have as big an impact on your life as the first $10 million. So, $20 million is not really "worth" twice as much as $10 million. The "infinite wager" solution to the St. Petersburg paradox assumes constant utility of money, even though that's not a realistic model of how people behave.
edited 8 hours ago
answered 8 hours ago
Nuclear WangNuclear Wang
1,391616
1,391616
1
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
add a comment |
1
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
1
1
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
$begingroup$
As a small addition to this (already good and complete) answer, I think it might be worth point out that for the paradox, you don't need the utility of money to be constant; you just need the utility of an unbounded amount of money to be unbounded. That is, no matter how much money you already have, there is always an amount of money that makes you 1% happier. Then simply replace each successive doubling of money with whatever number doubles the utility of the previous amount of money.
$endgroup$
– Mees de Vries
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I would pay you
All my money, and then be sad when I lost it all on the first flip
because
Let the amount I pay you be represented as C. After paying C, you have a 1/2 chance of winning 0, a 1/4 chance of winning 1, a 1/8 chance of winning 2, a 1/16 chance of winning 4 etc. Your expected payout would be $$-C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{2^{i+2}}2^i = -C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{4} = -C + infty$$ Theoretically if you played forever and ever, you would profit no matter how much you paid per game. Realistically, you would probably not profit no matter how much you paid.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I would pay you
All my money, and then be sad when I lost it all on the first flip
because
Let the amount I pay you be represented as C. After paying C, you have a 1/2 chance of winning 0, a 1/4 chance of winning 1, a 1/8 chance of winning 2, a 1/16 chance of winning 4 etc. Your expected payout would be $$-C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{2^{i+2}}2^i = -C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{4} = -C + infty$$ Theoretically if you played forever and ever, you would profit no matter how much you paid per game. Realistically, you would probably not profit no matter how much you paid.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I would pay you
All my money, and then be sad when I lost it all on the first flip
because
Let the amount I pay you be represented as C. After paying C, you have a 1/2 chance of winning 0, a 1/4 chance of winning 1, a 1/8 chance of winning 2, a 1/16 chance of winning 4 etc. Your expected payout would be $$-C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{2^{i+2}}2^i = -C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{4} = -C + infty$$ Theoretically if you played forever and ever, you would profit no matter how much you paid per game. Realistically, you would probably not profit no matter how much you paid.
$endgroup$
I would pay you
All my money, and then be sad when I lost it all on the first flip
because
Let the amount I pay you be represented as C. After paying C, you have a 1/2 chance of winning 0, a 1/4 chance of winning 1, a 1/8 chance of winning 2, a 1/16 chance of winning 4 etc. Your expected payout would be $$-C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{2^{i+2}}2^i = -C + sum_{i=0}^infty frac{1}{4} = -C + infty$$ Theoretically if you played forever and ever, you would profit no matter how much you paid per game. Realistically, you would probably not profit no matter how much you paid.
answered 8 hours ago
PunPun1000PunPun1000
38615
38615
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
There are several nuances to this question. First of all, it asks how much you are willing to pay, not what price is fair. Second, you have to understand, that even if a game is fair, that does not mean that It is reasonable to play it.
For example, if someone offers me a one in a million chance to win a million dollars for 1, I will take it. It seems reasonable. But if someone offered me a one in a million chance to win a billion dollars for 1000, I would not. What’s the difference? I am willing to lose a dollar for a small chance at success, but I am not willing to lose a thousand dollars for that same small chance, even if the reward is adjusted accordingly.
You have to factor in how much money you are willing to lose if the game does not go your way, especially if you only play once.
Since there is a 50% chance to lose your whole wager, the question becomes how much is the reward, but also how much are you willing to lose for it? If the reward was a million dollars, I would not wager 500,000 for a 50% chance to lose it, even if that is a “fair” game.
Realistically, I know the chance of getting a long streak of heads in a row is very low. Even though in 100 coin flips it’s not uncommon to have several streaks of 5 to 7 heads or tails in a row, playing the game only once means that the law of large numbers doesn’t apply.
For these reasons, I would not wager more than $1 for this game, because I don’t expect to see more than 3 heads in a row.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
There are several nuances to this question. First of all, it asks how much you are willing to pay, not what price is fair. Second, you have to understand, that even if a game is fair, that does not mean that It is reasonable to play it.
For example, if someone offers me a one in a million chance to win a million dollars for 1, I will take it. It seems reasonable. But if someone offered me a one in a million chance to win a billion dollars for 1000, I would not. What’s the difference? I am willing to lose a dollar for a small chance at success, but I am not willing to lose a thousand dollars for that same small chance, even if the reward is adjusted accordingly.
You have to factor in how much money you are willing to lose if the game does not go your way, especially if you only play once.
Since there is a 50% chance to lose your whole wager, the question becomes how much is the reward, but also how much are you willing to lose for it? If the reward was a million dollars, I would not wager 500,000 for a 50% chance to lose it, even if that is a “fair” game.
Realistically, I know the chance of getting a long streak of heads in a row is very low. Even though in 100 coin flips it’s not uncommon to have several streaks of 5 to 7 heads or tails in a row, playing the game only once means that the law of large numbers doesn’t apply.
For these reasons, I would not wager more than $1 for this game, because I don’t expect to see more than 3 heads in a row.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
There are several nuances to this question. First of all, it asks how much you are willing to pay, not what price is fair. Second, you have to understand, that even if a game is fair, that does not mean that It is reasonable to play it.
For example, if someone offers me a one in a million chance to win a million dollars for 1, I will take it. It seems reasonable. But if someone offered me a one in a million chance to win a billion dollars for 1000, I would not. What’s the difference? I am willing to lose a dollar for a small chance at success, but I am not willing to lose a thousand dollars for that same small chance, even if the reward is adjusted accordingly.
You have to factor in how much money you are willing to lose if the game does not go your way, especially if you only play once.
Since there is a 50% chance to lose your whole wager, the question becomes how much is the reward, but also how much are you willing to lose for it? If the reward was a million dollars, I would not wager 500,000 for a 50% chance to lose it, even if that is a “fair” game.
Realistically, I know the chance of getting a long streak of heads in a row is very low. Even though in 100 coin flips it’s not uncommon to have several streaks of 5 to 7 heads or tails in a row, playing the game only once means that the law of large numbers doesn’t apply.
For these reasons, I would not wager more than $1 for this game, because I don’t expect to see more than 3 heads in a row.
$endgroup$
There are several nuances to this question. First of all, it asks how much you are willing to pay, not what price is fair. Second, you have to understand, that even if a game is fair, that does not mean that It is reasonable to play it.
For example, if someone offers me a one in a million chance to win a million dollars for 1, I will take it. It seems reasonable. But if someone offered me a one in a million chance to win a billion dollars for 1000, I would not. What’s the difference? I am willing to lose a dollar for a small chance at success, but I am not willing to lose a thousand dollars for that same small chance, even if the reward is adjusted accordingly.
You have to factor in how much money you are willing to lose if the game does not go your way, especially if you only play once.
Since there is a 50% chance to lose your whole wager, the question becomes how much is the reward, but also how much are you willing to lose for it? If the reward was a million dollars, I would not wager 500,000 for a 50% chance to lose it, even if that is a “fair” game.
Realistically, I know the chance of getting a long streak of heads in a row is very low. Even though in 100 coin flips it’s not uncommon to have several streaks of 5 to 7 heads or tails in a row, playing the game only once means that the law of large numbers doesn’t apply.
For these reasons, I would not wager more than $1 for this game, because I don’t expect to see more than 3 heads in a row.
edited 3 hours ago
answered 3 hours ago
AmorydaiAmorydai
1,608215
1,608215
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I will pay you
One dollar
to play this game, because
The amount you pay me has no bearing on what I pay you.
If there was a single throw there would be 50-50 chance of getting my dollar back.
But the game can go on, so there is better than 50-50 of getting my dollar back.
Your bankroll is the limit — your house against my $1.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I will pay you
One dollar
to play this game, because
The amount you pay me has no bearing on what I pay you.
If there was a single throw there would be 50-50 chance of getting my dollar back.
But the game can go on, so there is better than 50-50 of getting my dollar back.
Your bankroll is the limit — your house against my $1.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I will pay you
One dollar
to play this game, because
The amount you pay me has no bearing on what I pay you.
If there was a single throw there would be 50-50 chance of getting my dollar back.
But the game can go on, so there is better than 50-50 of getting my dollar back.
Your bankroll is the limit — your house against my $1.
$endgroup$
I will pay you
One dollar
to play this game, because
The amount you pay me has no bearing on what I pay you.
If there was a single throw there would be 50-50 chance of getting my dollar back.
But the game can go on, so there is better than 50-50 of getting my dollar back.
Your bankroll is the limit — your house against my $1.
answered 8 hours ago
Weather VaneWeather Vane
2,545113
2,545113
1
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
add a comment |
1
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
1
1
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Why not pay one penny instead of a whole dollar? Alternatively, if the game was offered for $1.01, you would reject the offer?
$endgroup$
– Nuclear Wang
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@NuclearWang please don't reveal the hidden answer. In answer to your question, because in the land of this puzzle I don't know if a penny exists. But I do know that the amount I stated exists.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Your answer to @NuclearWang ignores his/her second question. Replace 1.01 by 2 if you like it better, the point of the question is the same.
$endgroup$
– Arnaud Mortier
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@ArnaudMortier the game is not being offered to me for $1.01 or 2 and it is not Nuclear Wang's puzzle. The question was: How much will I pay? And that was my answer.
$endgroup$
– Weather Vane
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
$begingroup$
"Note, this is not a loophole question".
$endgroup$
– SpqrTiang
5 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To play once I would pay:
50 cents, since it is a doubling game and one heads is a dollar.
New contributor
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To play once I would pay:
50 cents, since it is a doubling game and one heads is a dollar.
New contributor
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To play once I would pay:
50 cents, since it is a doubling game and one heads is a dollar.
New contributor
$endgroup$
To play once I would pay:
50 cents, since it is a doubling game and one heads is a dollar.
New contributor
edited 7 hours ago
New contributor
answered 8 hours ago
likwidfire2klikwidfire2k
113
113
New contributor
New contributor
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Brutal with the downvotes when updating answers...
$endgroup$
– likwidfire2k
7 hours ago
add a comment |
SpqrTiang is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
SpqrTiang is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
SpqrTiang is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
SpqrTiang is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
Thanks for contributing an answer to Puzzling Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fpuzzling.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f82060%2fcoin-game-with-infinite-paradox%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
4
$begingroup$
This is known as St Petersburg paradox.en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/St._Petersburg_paradox
$endgroup$
– Tojrah
9 hours ago